Austin
The modern study
of speech acts begins with Austin’s (1962) engaging monograph
How to Do
Things with Words, the published version of his William James
Lectures delivered at Harvard in 1955. This widely cited work starts with the
observation that certain sorts of sentences, e.g., I christen this ship the
Joseph Stalin; I now pronounce you man and wife, and the like, seem designed to do something, here to christen and wed,
respectively, rather than merely to say something. Such sentences Austin dubbed performatives, in
contrast to what he called constatives, the descriptive sentences that until Austin were the
principal concern of philosophers of language – sentences that seem,
pretheoretically, at least, to be employed mainly for saying something rather
than doing something.
While the
distinction between performatives and constatives is often invoked in work on
the law, in literary criticism, in political analysis, and in other areas, it
is a distinction that Austin argued was not ultimately defensible.
The point of
Austin’s lectures was, in fact, that every normal utterance has both a descriptive and an effective aspect:
that saying something is also doing something.
Locutions,
illocutions, and perlocutions
In place of the
initial distinction between constatives and performatives, Austin substituted a
three-way contrast among the kinds of acts that are performed when language is
put to use, namely the distinction between locutionary, illocutionary, and
perlocutionary acts, all of which are characteristic of most utterances,
including standard examples of both performatives and constatives.
Locutionary acts, according to Austin, are acts of speaking, acts
involved in the construction of speech, such as uttering certain sounds or
making certain marks, using particular words and using them in conformity with
the grammatical rules of a particular language and with certain senses and
certain references as determined by the rules of the language from which they
are drawn.
Illocutionary
acts, Austin’s central innovation, are acts
done in speaking (hence illocutionary), including and especially that sort of act that is
the apparent purpose for using a performative sentence:
christening, marrying, and so forth. Austin called attention to the fact that
acts of stating or asserting, which are presumably illocutionary acts, are
characteristic of the use of canonical constatives, and such sentences are, by
assumption, not performatives.
Furthermore, acts
of ordering or requesting are typically accomplished by using imperative
sentences, and acts of asking whether something is the case are properly
accomplished by using interrogative sentences, though such forms are at best
very dubious examples of performative sentences. In Lecture XXI of Austin
(1962), the conclusion was drawn that the locutionary aspect of speaking is
what we attend to most in the case of constatives, while in the case of the standard
examples of performative sentences; we attend as much as possible to the illocution.
The third of
Austin’s categories of acts is the perlocutionary act, which is a consequence or by-product of
speaking, whether intended or not. As the name is designed to suggest,
perlocutions are acts performed by speaking. According to
Austin, perlocutionary acts consist in the production of effects upon the
thoughts, feelings, or actions of the addressee(s), speaker, or other parties,
such as causing people to refer to a certain ship as the Joseph Stalin, producing
the belief that Sam and Mary should be considered man and wife, convincing an
addressee of the truth of a statement, causing an addressee to feel a
requirement to do something, and so on.
Austin (1962: 101) illustrates the
distinction between these kinds of acts with the (now politically incorrect)
example of saying “Shoot her!,” which he trisects as follows:
Act (A) or
Locution
He said to me
“Shoot her!” meaning by shoot “shoot” and referring by her
to “her.”
Act (B) or
Illocution
He urged (or
advised, ordered, etc.) me to shoot her.
Act (C) or
Perlocution
He persuaded me
to shoot her.
Austin
classifies illocutionary acts into five types, i.e., verdictives, exercitives, commissives,
behabitives, and expositives. Although it is often argued that Austin’s
classification is not complete and those coined categories are not mutually
exclusive, Austin’s classification is best seen as an attempt to give a general
picture of illocutionary acts: what types of illocutionary act one can
generally perform in uttering a sentence. One can exercise judgment
(Verdictive), exert influence or exercise power (Exercitive), assume obligation
or declare intention (Commissive), adopt attitude, or express feeling
(Behabitive), and clarify reasons, argument, or communication (Expositive). The
long list of illocutionary verbs in each class also illustrates how many subtly
differentiated illocutionary acts exist in a language like English. The fact
that Austin includes the same word in two different classes and he does not
regard it as a problem suggests that it is not an issue for Austin which class
a particular illocutionary verb/act actually belongs to. The importance of
introducing this classification of illocutionary acts is rather to explicate,
as we explained above, what type of illocutionary act one can generally perform
by uttering a sentence; and, with additional specifications, how much more
diversified illocutionary acts are than we are usually aware of. The purpose of
the classification of illocutionary acts, if interpreted in this manner, is
compatible with Austin’s beliefs as a major proponent of Ordinary Language
Philosophy, which is typically expressed in remarks such as the following:
our common stock
of words embodies all the distinctions men have found worth drawing, and the
connexions they have found worth marking, in the lifetimes of many generations:
these surely are likely to be more numerous, more sound, since they have stood
up to the long test of the survival of the fittest, and more subtle, at least
in all ordinary and reasonably practical matters, than any that you or I are
likely to think up in our arm-chairs of an afternoon — the most favored
alternative method. (Austin 1961: 182)
To Summarize:
Felicity conditions: expected or
appropriate circumstances for a speech act to be recognized as intended I
sentence you to six months in prison - performance will be infelicitous if
the speaker is not a judge in a courtroom
General conditions: language is understood, no
play-acting, nonsense
Content conditions: e.g. for promises/warnings the
content of the utterance must be about a future event (promise: the event will
be an act by the speaker)
Preparatory conditions: pre-existing
conditions about the event, e.g., promise: event will not happen by itself,
event will be beneficial warning: it's not clear if the hearer knows that the
event will occur, the event will not have a beneficial effect
Sincerity conditions: attitude of
the speaker, e.g., promise: speaker genuinely intends to carry out the future
action warning: speaker genuinely believes the future event will not have a
beneficial effect
Essential conditions: change of state in the speaker, e.g., promise: change of state
from non-obligation to obligation to carry out action warning: change of state
from non-information of bad future event to information
SEARLE
In Searle 1969, 24-25, the author presents a theory
which is a development of the account presented in Austin 1962. Searle claims
that four acts are characteristically performed in the utterance of a sentence:
a. Uttering words (morphemes, sentences) = performing utterance acts
b. Referring and predicating = performing propositional acts
c. Stating, questioning, commanding, promising etc. =
performing illocutionary acts
In
general, Searle’s theory of speech acts is just Austin’s systematized, in part
rigidified, with sallies into the general theory of meaning, and connections to
other philosophical issues. Austin thought that one could come to an
interesting classification through taxonomy of performative verbs, but Searle
seeks some more abstract scheme based on felicity conditions. In fact, he
proposes that there are just five basic kinds of action that one can perform in
speaking, by means of the following five types of utterance:
1. Representatives, which commit the speaker
to the truth of the expressed proposition (paradigm cases: asserting,
concluding, etc.)
2. Directives, which are attempts by the
speaker to get the addressee to do something (paradigm cases: requesting,
questioning)
3. Commissives, which commit the speaker to
some future course of action (paradigm cases: promising, threatening, offering)
4. Expressive, which express a psychological
state (paradigm cases: thanking, apologizing, welcoming, and congratulating)
5. Declarations, which effect immediate
changes in the institutional state of affairs and which tend to rely on
elaborate extra – linguistic institutions (paradigm cases: excommunicating,
declaring war, christening, firing from employment)
To Searle,
as with Austin, the illocutionary act is directly achieved by the conventional
force associated with the issuance of a certain kind of utterance in accord
with a conventional procedure. In contrast, a perlocutionary act is
specific to circumstances of issuance, and is therefore not conventionally
achieved just by uttering that particular utterance, and includes all those
effects, intended or unintended, often indeterminate, that some particular
utterance in some particular situation may cause.
No comments:
Post a Comment